The Ego and his Own - Max Stirner (ebook reader screen .TXT) 📗
- Author: Max Stirner
- Performer: -
Book online «The Ego and his Own - Max Stirner (ebook reader screen .TXT) 📗». Author Max Stirner
throng of aphorisms... But, if you read this book several times; if, after
having penetrated the intimacy of each of its parts, you then traverse it as a
whole, -- gradually the fragments weld themselves together, and Stirner's
thought is revealed in all its unity, in all its force, and in all its depth."
A word about the dedication. Mackay's investigations have brought to light
that Marie Dähnhardt had nothing whatever in common with Stirner, and so was
unworthy of the honor conferred upon her. She was no Eigene. I therefore
reproduce the dedication merely in the interest of historical accuracy.
Happy as I am in the appearance of this book, my joy is not unmixed with
sorrow. The cherished project was as dear to the heart of Dr. Walker as to
mine, and I deeply grieve that he is no longer with us to share our delight in
the fruition. Nothing, however, can rob us of the masterly introduction that
he wrote for this volume (in 1903, or perhaps earlier), from which I will not
longer keep the reader. This introduction, no more than the book itself, shall
that Einzige, Death, make his Eigentum.
February, 1907.
B. R. T.
---- * ----
INTRODUCTION
Fifty years sooner or later can make little difference in the; case of a book
so revolutionary as this. It saw the light when a so-called revolutionary
movement was preparing in men's minds which agitation was, however, only a
disturbance due to desires to participate in government, and to govern and to
be governed, in a manner different to that which prevails. The
"revolutionists" of 1848 were bewitched with an idea. They were not at all the
masters of ideas. Most of those who since that time have prided themselves
upon being revolutionists have been and are likewise but the bondmen of an
idea, -- that of the different lodgment of authority.
The temptation is, of course, present to attempt an explanation of the central
thought of this work; but such an effort appears to be unnecessary to one who
has the volume in his hand. The author's care in illustrating his meaning
shows that he realized how prone the possessed man is to misunderstand
whatever is not moulded according to the fashions in thinking. The author's
learning was considerable, his command of words and ideas may never be
excelled by another, and he judged it needful to develop his argument in
manifold ways. So those who enter into the spirit of it will scarcely hope to
impress others with the same conclusion in a more summary manner. Or, if one
might deem that possible after reading Stirner, still one cannot think that it
could be done so surely. The author has made certain work of it, even though
he has to wait for his public; but still, the reception of the book by its
critics amply proves the truth of the saying that one can give another
arguments, but not understanding. The system-makers and system-believers thus
far cannot get it out of their heads that any discourse about the nature of an
ego must turn upon the common characteristics of egos, to make a systematic
scheme of what they share as a generality. The critics inquire what kind of
man the author is talking about. They repeat the question: What does he
believe in? They fail to grasp the purport of the recorded answer: "I believe
in myself"; which is attributed to a common soldier long before the time of
Stirner. They ask, what is the principle of the self-conscious egoist, the
Einzige? To this perplexity Stirner says: Change the question; put "who?"
instead of "what?" and an answer can then be given by naming him!
This, of course, is too simple for persons governed by ideas, and for persons
in quest of new governing ideas. They wish to classify the man. Now, that in
me which you can classify is not my distinguishing self. "Man" is the horizon
or zero of my existence as an individual. Over that I rise as I can. At least
I am something more than "man in general." Pre-existing worship of ideals and
disrespect for self had made of the ego at the very most a Somebody, oftener
an empty vessel to be filled with the grace or the leavings of a tyrannous
doctrine; thus a Nobody. Stirner dispels the morbid subjection, and recognizes
each one who knows and feels himself as his own property to be neither humble
Nobody nor befogged Somebody, but henceforth flat-footed and level-headed Mr.
Thisbody, who has a character and good pleasure of his own, just as he has a
name of his own. The critics who attacked this work and were answered in the
author's minor writings, rescued from oblivion by John Henry Mackay, nearly
all display the most astonishing triviality and impotent malice.
We owe to Dr. Eduard von Hartmann the unquestionable service which he rendered
by directing attention to this book in his "Philosophie des Unbewußten," the
first edition of which was published in 1869, and in other writings. I do not
begrudge Dr. von Hartmann the liberty of criticism which he used; and I think
the admirers of Stirner's teaching must quite appreciate one thing which Von
Hartmann did at a much later date. In "Der Eigene" of August 10, 1896, there
appeared a letter written by him and giving, among other things, certain data
from which to judge that, when Friedrich Nietzsche wrote his later essays,
Nietzsche was not ignorant of Stirner's book.
Von Hartmann wishes that Stirner had gone on and developed his principle. Von
Hartmann suggests that you and I are really the same spirit, looking out
through two pairs of eyes. Then, one may reply, I need not concern myself
about you, for in myself I have -- us; and at that rate Von Hartmann is merely
accusing himself of inconsistency: for, when Stirner wrote this book, Von
Hartmann's spirit was writing it; and it is just the pity that Von Hartmann in
his present form does not indorse what he said in the form of Stirner, -- that
Stirner was different from any other man; that his ego was not Fichte's
transcendental generality, but "this transitory ego of flesh and blood." It is
not as a generality that you and I differ, but as a couple of facts which are
not to be reasoned into one. "I" is somewise Hartmann, and thus Hartmann is
"I"; but I am not Hartmann, and Hartmann is not -- I. Neither am I the "I" of
Stirner; only Stirner himself was Stirner's "I." Note how comparatively
indifferent a matter it is with Stirner that one is an ego, but how
all-important it is that one be a self-conscious ego, -- a self-conscious,
self-willed person.
Those not self-conscious and self-willed are constantly acting from
self-interested motives, but clothing these in various garbs. Watch those
people closely in the light of Stirner's teaching, and they seem to be
hypocrites, they have so many good moral and religious plans of which
self-interest is at the end and bottom; but they, we may believe, do not know
that this is more than a coincidence.
In Stirner we have the philosophical foundation for political liberty. His
interest in the practical development of egoism to the dissolution of the
State and the union of free men is clear and pronounced, and harmonizes
perfectly with the economic philosophy of Josiah Warren. Allowing for
difference of temperament and language, there is a substantial agreement
between Stirner and Proudhon. Each would be free, and sees in every increase
of the number of free people and their intelligence an auxiliary force against
the oppressor. But, on the other hand, will any one for a moment seriously
contend that Nietzsche and Proudhon march together in general aim and
tendency, -- that they have anything in common except the daring to profane
the shrine and sepulchre of superstition?
Nietzsche has been much spoken of as a disciple of Stirner, and, owing to
favorable cullings from Nietzsche's writings, it has occurred that one of his
books has been supposed to contain more sense than it really does -- so long
as one had read only the extracts.
Nietzsche cites scores or hundreds of authors. Had he read everything, and not
read Stirner?
But Nietzsche is as unlike Stirner as a tight-rope performance is unlike an
algebraic equation.
Stirner loved liberty for himself, and loved to see any and all men and women
taking liberty, and he had no lust of power. Democracy to him was sham
liberty, egoism the genuine liberty.
Nietzsche, on the contrary, pours out his contempt upon democracy because it
is not aristocratic. He is predatory to the point of demanding that those who
must succumb to feline rapacity shall be taught to submit with resignation.
When he speaks of "Anarchistic dogs" scouring the streets of great civilized
cities; it is true, the context shows that he means the Communists; but his
worship of Napoleon, his bathos of anxiety for the rise of an aristocracy that
shall rule Europe for thousands of years, his idea of treating women in the
oriental fashion, show that Nietzsche has struck out in a very old path --
doing the apotheosis of tyranny. We individual egoistic Anarchists, however,
may say to the Nietzsche school, so as not to be misunderstood: We do not ask
of the Napoleons to have pity, nor of the predatory barons to do justice. They
will find it convenient for their own welfare to make terms with men who have
learned of Stirner what a man can be who worships nothing, bears allegiance to
nothing. To Nietzsche's rhodomontade of eagles in baronial form, born to prey
on industrial lambs, we rather tauntingly oppose the ironical question: Where
are your claws? What if the "eagles" are found to be plain barn-yard fowls on
which more silly fowls have fastened steel spurs to hack the victims, who,
however, have the power to disarm the sham "eagles" between two suns? Stirner
shows that men make their tyrants as they make their gods, and his purpose is
to unmake tyrants.
Nietzsche dearly loves a tyrant.
In style Stirner's work offers the greatest possible contrast to the puerile,
padded phraseology of Nietzsche's "Zarathustra" and its false imagery. Who
ever imagined such an unnatural conjuncture as an eagle "toting" a serpent in
friendship? which performance is told of in bare words, but nothing comes of
it. In Stirner we are treated to an enlivening and earnest discussion
addressed to serious minds, and every reader feels that the word is to him,
for his instruction and benefit, so far as he has mental independence and
courage to take it and use it. The startling intrepidity of this book is
infused with a whole-hearted love for all mankind, as evidenced by the fact
that the author shows not one iota of prejudice or any idea of division of men
into ranks. He would lay aside government, but would establish any regulation
deemed convenient, and for this only our convenience in
Comments (0)